Section 1.14 A first look at induction
Recall that we defined the natural numbers as sets in an iterative fashion. We declare zero to be \(0 = \varnothing\text{,}\) and if \(n\) is a natural number, then its successor is the set \(n + 1 = S(n) = n\cup\{n\}\text{.}\)
Then the set of all natural numbers
is characterized in the following way. A set \(M\) is said to be successive if and only if \(0\in M\text{,}\) and for any \(A \in M\text{,}\) one has \(S(A)\in M\text{.}\) Now \(\NN_0\) is defined to be the smallest successive set; that is, \(\NN_0\) is the successive set such that no proper subset \(T \subset \NN_0\) is successive.
One fanstatic consequence of this definition is that it embodies the Principle of Mathematical Induction. Here's how that works. Let's say you've got a statement \(\phi(n)\) with a free variable \(n\text{,}\) and let's say that you suspect it's true for all natural numbers \(n\text{.}\) If you can prove \(\phi(0)\) as well as \((\forall m \in \NN_0)(\phi(m) \Longrightarrow \phi(m+1))\text{,}\) then you can conclude that every natural number has the property \(\phi\text{.}\)
Why is this true? Well, consider the set \(X = \{n\in \NN_0 : \phi(n)\}\) of all those natural numbers with property \(\phi\text{.}\) If you prove that \(\phi(0)\text{,}\) then you'll have shown that \(0\in X\text{.}\) If you prove that \((\forall m \in \NN_0)(\phi(m) \Longrightarrow \phi(m+1)\) as well, then you'll have shown that \(X\) is a successive set. But since no proper subset of \(\NN_0\) is successive, it follows that \(X=\NN_0\text{.}\) That means that for every natural number \(n\text{,}\) we have \(\phi(n)\text{.}\)
Why is this helpful? Induction gives us footholds for working our way up the tower of natural numbers. It is usually not so difficult to check \(\phi(0)\) by hand; this is sometimes called the base case for the induction. Then one wants to prove that, for every \(n\in\NN_0\text{,}\) the statement \(\phi(m)\) implies the statement \(\phi(m+1)\text{.}\) For this, one is allowed to assume \(\phi(m)\) (the induction hypothesis and to try to deduce \(\phi(m+1)\text{.}\)
Example 1.14.1. A simple induction argument.
Let us prove by induction that for any natural number \(n\text{,}\) one has
When \(n=0\text{,}\) this is the claim that \(0 = \frac{0\cdot 1}{2}\text{,}\) which is certainly true. Now let \(m\in\NN_0\text{,}\) and assume that
From this we deduce
Thus by the Principle of Mathematical Induction, we deduce that for any natural number \(n\text{,}\) one has
We will see many more examples, along with an elaboration of induction techniques, later in the course.